PAGINA NO OFICIAL DE CARLOS ESCUDE

ALGUNOS COMENTARIOS SOBRE SUS LIBROS



Foreign Policy Theory and the Peripheral State

James Cane, University of California-Berkeley.

"International relations theory is in a sad state both on the periphery and at the center," proclaims Carlos Escude in the final chapter of Foreign Policy Theory in Menem’s Argentina. For this Argentine political theorist, the problem of the lack of foreign policy theory relevant to those less-powerful states outside the international economic center is compounded by the relative poverty of foreign policy theory in general. "Not only is a theory being imported (by intellectuals and politicians of the periphery) that does not correspond to the local circumstances, but it also happens to be bad theory" (p. 128). Basing his work on the experience of Argentina under the momentous foreign policy shift of the Menem administration, Escude attempts to remedy this double deficiency by articulating a foreign policy theory of what he calls "peripheral realism." Like most ambitious and polemic theoretical undertakings, Escude’s project meets with uneven success.

Many of the shortcomings of the work may be compounded for readers more accustomed to historical analysis and methodology; others seem imbedded in the development of Escude’s arguments themselves. Nonetheless, Foreign Policy Theory in Menem’s Argentina does provide interesting insights into the workings of foreign policy in the periphery, while also calling attention to the unintended consequences of well-meaning theorists in the North. Escude dedicates a considerable portion of Foreign Policy Theory in Menem’s Argentina to refuting both the relevance and normative assumptions of international relations theory developed in the English-speaking world. Central to his critique is an examination of the frequent recurrence to "state-centric and anthropomorphic fallacies, that," he argues, "are not accidental blunders but the conventional language of the field, found very often in the literature" (p. 34). Citing examples from Keohane and Nye, John Garnet, Kenneth Waltz, and Richard Ashley, Escude convincingly demonstrates that linguistic slippage and frequent assumptions in the literature to the effect that states, like people, can suffer, be brought to their knees, feel pride and be humiliated, are often integral to the substance of the theories espoused.

As "victims of a mind-set in which states represent nations and the relations between nations are parallel to the relations between individual human beings," theorists of foreign relations easily fall into potentially dangerous traps of linguistic origin (p. 35). Few of us working in the field of history will see Escude’s critique of the potentially totalitarian effects of such anthropomorphic notions of the state and their potential to generate the "emotional behavior functional to the mobilization of loyalties toward the state" (p. 45) as earthshakingly new. Yet, Escude feels it imperative that his intended audience—international relations theorists—take the critique seriously, since they often unwittingly provide the ideological justifications for cunter-productive, confrontational foreign policies on the part of peripheral states: if theorists were more careful with their words, there would at least be no encouragement of Saddam Hussein by brilliant Ivy League professors who give to the world the ‘empirical, value-free’ statement that ‘poor, weak states may be more willing to suffer (the costs of international confrontation).’ Care in the use of words could make a difference, a small one maybe but a very real one in terms of the lives that it might save from time to time, if only because a petty tyrant lacked an available ideological justification for his latest folly (p. 45). Similarly, Escude’s argument against the notion, implicit in much international relations theory, that states are juridically equal players in the international arena will find little objection from historians. Escude points to GATT, the nuclear Non-Proliferation Treaty, the Missile Technology Control Regime, and, of course, the veto power of permanent members of the U.N. Security Council as clear indications that different states are not only unequal in terms of economic and military power, but are also unequal in terms of the normal functioning of major international institutions. By also alternately assuming that states on the periphery are of the same general nature as central states in terms of the correlation of economic power to military power, and/or that states are alike in their normative goal of maximizing an ill-defined and all-or-none "autonomy," Escude maintains, only further provides the ideological justification for draining the civilian economy for militaristic ends.

Escude’s answers to the distortions inherent in any theory that maintains the anthropomorphic notion of the state and/or fails to adequately address the many differences of central and peripheral states forms the basis for his own normative proposals. To the potential totalitarianism of careless abstractions of the "state," Escude counters with a call for a foreign policy based on the welfare of the majority of average citizens, rather than the issues of national "pride" that consistently benefit elites at the expense of non-elites.

Relatedly, he argues that governments of less-powerful states should build foreign policies around the recognition that their populations suffer significantly more than those of powerful states in international confrontations due to the disruptive effects of sanctions, the inflation of military budgets, and shaken investor confidence. Combining these notions with the concrete experience of Argentine foreign policy during the Menem administration, Escude presents five basic guidelines for the development of an effective foreign policy—or, a "realist theory of damage control"—on the part of peripheral states:

"(1) A peripheral government should abstain from interstate power politics and devote itself to promoting local economic development instead....

(2) It should abstain from costly idealistic interstate policies. A peripheral government should engage in promoting democracy, freedom, ecological conservation, or other good causes abroad only when it can do so without encouraging material costs or risks for itself and its people.

(3) It should abstain from risky confrontations with great powers when they engage in policies that are detrimental to universal good causes but that do not affect the peripheral government’s material interests....

(4) It should abstain from unproductive political confrontations with great powers, even when such confrontations have no immediate costs because of great powers’ reluctance to make use of image-damaging issue linkages. Such confrontations generate negative perceptions within the great powers that can be costly in the long term.

(5) And it should study, based on the merits of specific historical circumstances, the possibility of alignment or bandwagoning with a dominant or hegemonic power or power coalition" (pp. 87-89). Such a strategy, Escude maintains, provides the greatest possibilities that not only will external factors become less likely to interfere with the course of economic development, but that such a conciliatory foreign policy towards the important economic powers will bring much needed investment and trade due to greater confidence. The guidelines also cannot be reduced to mere realpolitik, since "peripheral realism is quite different from realpolitik, precisely because it is a realism for those who are deprived of power" (p. 93). I would venture to guess that most readers’ reactions to a foreign policy so deferential to the interests of the United States and other important economic powers would be as negative as that of this reviewer. Escude does, however, have a clear and at least partially convincing response: there is a considerable frivolity in the criticisms of such policies by liberal intellectuals, especially U.S. academicians. Because of their relative combativeness in the United States, they often enjoy the confrontations generated by Third World states and indirectly promote these policies, without bearing in mind what the costs may be to the countries and their people.

They fall into the same syndrome that affects many Third World leaders: they forget that what is at stake is often the welfare of millions of poor and hungry people, they think of countries in anthropomorphic terms, and they treat foreign policy as if it were the sport of states (pp. 97-98). The author does not consider—nor is it necessarily his concern—that any open endorsement of such policies by U.S. academicians would obviously bring on calls of imperialism. Such answers to potential criticism, as resonant as they might be, however, assume that the substance and internal logic of Escude’s theorizing is beyond reproach.

This is clearly not the case. In fact, despite the integrity of his critique of the linguistically-generated traps into which Anglo-American theorists inadvertently fall, Escude himself centers his theoretical project on a term loaded with different historical and political levels of meaning: "socioeconomic development." Thus, despite his pleas that foreign policy theorists choose their language carefully and provide clear definitions of important terms, Escude himself fails to follow his own advice—extensive sections of operational definitions notwithstanding. While Escude writes that "from a peripheral perspective under contractarian, liberal democratic, and mercantilist assumptions, socioeconomic development is the very definition of the national interest; the principal function of a peripheral state’s foreign policy is to facilitate development," he nonetheless fails to define "socioeconomic development."

The oversight is far from inconsequential. In fact, by assuming that the very narrow definition which the term has only recently taken is historically constant, Escude not surprisingly finds himself unable to explain adequately—at least for this reviewer—why Argentine foreign policy might ever have differed from its current incarnation. Holding past architects of foreign policy to today’s standards, Escude seems unaware that it was not very long ago at all that a not insignificant segment of the country’s political spectrum held as common sense the notion that massive foreign investment was actually inimicable to "socioeconomic development." Current objections to the Menem foreign policy strategy, then, may also lie not so much with misconceptions of the nature of the state, but with differing definitions of what is essentially the goal to be pursued. Similarly, by not taking into account shifting conceptions of development, Escude sees few objections to his claim that, at least in the short term, the collapse of the Soviet Union and the Eastern European socialisms and other "major changes in the interstate system as have occurred recently are relatively irrelevant" (p. 90). It is precisely on the conception of "socioeconomic development," so central to Escude’s project, however, that the changes of 1989-90 are momentous. The nearly overnight elimination of an economic arrangement that, regardless of its real or perceived shortcomings, seemed a viable alternative to that of late capitalism, is hardly "irrelevant." The very existence of the USSR—even for those who rejected it as a model—belied the possibility that "socioeconomic development" could, in fact, take multiple courses, perhaps as many as there are regions on the globe. Thus, when Escude quotes former president Raul Alfonsin proclaiming in 1986 that Argentina must "define its own road to development" (p. 123), he nonetheless ignores the fact that a road different from that of massive privatization, radical market orientation, and accommodation to foreign capital was only recently imaginable, if not practical.

That the current opposition Alianza—an awkward conglomeration of Radicals, dissident Peronists, Socialists, and Communists, among others—promises no substantive economic changes should it assume power only confirms the extent to which the changes of the early 1990s are entirely relevant. Is it merely coincidence that the radical shift in Argentine economic policy and foreign policy (just one of many such shifts in the region) should coincide with the fierce restructuring and massive geographic expansion of a particular form of capitalism, as well as the related dramatic shift in political alliances? Escude’s failure to clearly articulate the ultimate goal of his foreign policy prescriptions is even more confusing given his own political-economic stance: in terms of its internal logic, the foreign policy model here proposed is not of necessity associated with the market liberalism adopted by the Menem administration as its economic model.

In principle there is no reason why the peripheral realism developed in this book (a fair depiction of Argentina’s present-day foreign policies) should not be congenial with a social-democratic economic model, which I would actually prefer (p. 21). Yet, one cannot help but see his description of peripheral realist foreign policy as intimately related to political and economic neoliberalism, rather than easily separable. At the very least, Escude’s implicit claim that the definition of "socioeconomic development" can be left to democratic domestic political debate with no effect on his foreign policy prescriptions should be subject to the same rigorous critical standards that he has set for other theorists. Here it is not. That the Menem administration’s current move to moderate its economic model in hopes of achieving a third presidential term threatens imminently to tax the goodwill and confidence that the administration has gained in part through its foreign policy seems to contradict the disjunction. Despite these failings, Foreign Policy Theory in Menem’s Argentina, does, however, provide an interesting basis for future work in both the theoretical, practical, and research realms. One can only hope that Escude soon plans to turn his keen critical insight and intellectual integrity toward a companion empirical study of the foreign policy shift under Menem that would explore the ideological and material links between the administration’s foreign policy and the massive restructuring of Argentine society of the last decade.


Biografía apócrifa de Andrés Carvajal. Grupo Editor Latinoamericano, 1996.

Comentario de la contratapa del libro.

Hacia 1998, después del fracaso del Plan de Convertibilidad, la Argentina queda entrampada una vez más en un ciclo de violencia y lucha de facciones, en que el extremismo de derecha gana un importante espacio político. En ese contexto, una banda integrista, asociada a los carapintadas y simpatizante del fundamentalismo islámico, que se adjudica responsabilidad en la voladura de la Embajada de Israel y de la AMIA, secuestra a Andrés Carvajal y lo somete a un proceso parajudicial. El "sujeto" es acusado de traición a la Patria, subversión moral y conspiración sacrílega. La principal prueba de los acusadores es el Diario del Sujeto, donde se registra una trayectoria que, desde la sensibilidad de los fundamentalistas, es claramente autocondenatoria. La novela consiste en un diálogo permanente entre las confesiones del Diario y las acusaciones del Compilador, donde a partir de las vicisitudes de la vida del Sujeto, se pasa revista a las últimas tres décadas de historia argentina.

"Una obra de ficción anclada en la vida cotidiana y política de la Argentina contemporánea. Un rompecabezas para armar. Un juego ambiguo e inquietante de identidades que se contraponen y se entrecruzan. Un ensayo de reflexión sobre la experiencia de un sujeto colectivo que quiso reinventarlo todo: política, religión, sexualidad... Un contrapunto entre una generación que "sabía" qué es lo moral y cuál es el deber ser, y otra que frente al saber absoluto de sus padres se quedó sin verdades. Una extraña reflexión sobre el bien y el mal que no parte del moralismo. Un replegarse a la propia interioridad que se torna exterioridad porque la fuerza introspectiva rompe el límite entre el adentro y el afuera. Una conjunción en la que no hay contradicción entre el sentimiento literal y el alegórico. Un género nuevo y posmoderno".

Diana de Jerusalén.

 


Review de Foreign Policy Theory in Menem's Argentina, efectuado por los editores (University Press of Florida).

Carlos Escude explains the rationale for dramatic changes in Argentina's foreign policy following the inauguration of President Carlos Menem in 1989.

After decades of confrontation with the West, Argentina has abandoned an intermediate-range ballistic missile project, left the nonaligned movement, thrown in with the United States in the Gulf War, reestablished friendly relations with Britain, and undertaken a course of unilateral disarmament. Escude argues that these changes reflect Argentina's recognition that citizens of poor and vulnerable nations are asked to pay the price of attempts to engage in power politics and that those attempts often endanger the nation's citizens and increase its subordination in world affairs.

Moreover, he argues that mainstream international relations theory tends to obscure such processes by dealing with states as if they were individuals whose ultimate priority is "survival," or political independence. The state-as-person fiction generalized in I-R discourse obscures the fact that in a democracy the citizens and not the state are paramount. Following this distinction to its logical consequences, Escude undertakes a thorough deconstruction of I-R theory from a "citizen-centric" perspective - the perspective, he argues, that has inspired the Menem government's dovish foreign policies.


Comentario publicado en la contratapa de El realismo de los Estados débiles

En este libro, el autor nos demuestra con claridad casi matemática cómo toda la teoría de las relaciones internacionales acuñada en el mundo anglo-norteamericana, incluso la de la llamada escuela "liberal", traiciona la teoría liberal del Estado en que supuestamente se basan las sociedades occidentales. Por cierto, la teoría de las relaciones internacionales trata a los Estados como si fueran individuos, cuyo fin último es la supervivencia. Pero, arguye el autor, tratar a los Estados como si fueran individuos supone olvidar que por debajo de los Estados están los indidivuos propiamente dichos, lo que es particularmente grave si se recuerda que para la filosofía liberal la única razón-de-ser del Estado es servir al individuo. Más aún, si de Estados se trata, la "supervivencia" es sinónimo de "independencia", es decir, supervivencia política. ¿Qué precio están dispuestos a pagar los individuos por la supervivencia política de su Estado? Sin duda que un precio variable según circunstancias históricas, a pesar de lo que los fundamentalistas del nacionalismo quieren hacernos creer. La independencia no es un valor absoluto, mientras que la libertad del individuo, y su derecho a contribuir a determinar cuáles son los límites de los sacrificios que el Estado puede imponerle, sí lo es. La que aquí se presenta es una filosofía de política exterior hecha a la medida de esta Argentina en la que nos toca vivir, posterior a la destrucción del misil Cóndor II, a la abolición del servicio militar obligatorio y al desmantelamiento de su industria de defensa. Esta es una filosofía postmoderna de la abdicación. ¿Qué abdicación? La de las élites de los Estados débiles, cuyo imperativo categórico es renunciar a su (muy limitado) poder frente al mundo, en aras del bienestar de los ciudadanos de su país. A su vez, el bienestar ciudadano se entroniza como valor supremo de los Estados débiles, desplazando al patriotismo, o más bien convirtiéndose en la única fuente posible de un patriotismo legítimo.

Sobre el autor de esta página | Enviar comentarios | Cómo aportar material


REGRESA A PAGINA PRINCIPAL